Here are a couple of examples of ‘problem-based thinking’:
If people have access to guns, some small number of them will misuse those guns. That’s a ‘problem’, and the ‘solution’ is to take guns away from everyone.
If people have access to drugs, some small number of them will misuse those drugs. That’s a ‘problem’, and the ‘solution’ is to take drugs away from everyone.
But really, these are just special cases of a more general ‘problem’:
If people have freedom, some small number of them will misuse that freedom. That’s a ‘problem’, and the ‘solution’ is to take freedom away from everyone.
But consider Daniel in the lion’s den. Does he have a problem? Or is he just experiencing the consequences of his refusal to compromise his beliefs?
Or consider Jesus, about to be crucified. Does he have a problem? Or is he just experiencing the consequences of accepting his identity?
What about Socrates? Joan of Arc? Thomas More? Nathan Hale? The signers of the Declaration of Independence? Problems or consequences?
Would we want any of them to compromise their principles in order to get a different outcome? In fact, don’t we hold them up as examples of why it’s important not to do that?
If we adopt some principles, and they lead to certain undesirable consequences, then that’s just something we live with, and try to prepare for.
(The ultimate expression of this would be our state motto. No, not the new one, ‘Public Health Trumps Everything‘. I’m talking about the old, untruncated version: ‘Live Free or Die. Death is not the worst of evils.’)
But as soon as we call one of those consequences a ‘problem’, we flip the normal process (‘Be true to your principles, and accept whatever follows from that’) on its head.
Suddenly the most important thing isn’t following some principles, but obtaining some outcome; and the fact that there’s a ‘problem’ means that everyone will look for a ‘solution’, even when that’s not appropriate.
For example: We don’t have a ‘gun violence problem’, or an ‘opioid use problem’, or a ‘disinformation problem’. In each of those cases, what we have is a ‘consequence of freedom for which some of us have not adequately prepared’.
Given the inherently lazy and short-sighted nature of political processes, the ‘solutions’ to various ‘problems’ will invariably require ignoring, or even reversing, some of the principles that we have long declared to be essential.
Someone has been shot? Let’s take away guns! Someone has said something hurtful? Let’s outlaw unpopular speech! Someone might get away with a crime? Let’s presume guilt instead of innocence! And so on.
As Confucius noted, the first step towards wisdom is to call things by their right names. So the first step away from wisdom would be to call things by their wrong names.
The surest way to accelerate the erosion of our rights is to continue to elevate outcomes above principles, which begins by talking about consequences as if they are problems.